You are here:   Civilisation >  Books > Unreliable Lives of the Saints
 

St Augustine: A highly original, if unsystematic, theologian, depicted here by Botticelli

Apart from Aristotle, Augustine and Aquinas were the two thinkers who, more than any others, shaped the intellectual life of Western Europe in the long period from the early fifth to the end of the 17th century. Augustine gave Latin Christianity its characteristic emphases on Original Sin and grace, and a God at once Platonically immutable and outside time, but exercising his will contingently. Aquinas was, in his own day —the later 13th century, when Christian thinkers first began to use the whole range of Aristotle's works — a respected but controversial figure, one among a number of outstanding and influential theologians. In the 16th and 17th centuries, however, he became for Catholics a doctrinal authority matched only by Augustine. Although the intellectual history of these two centuries is often portrayed, in retrospect, as a conflict between scholasticism and modern science, it would be truer to see the time as one of struggle between these two giants of its past, Augustine and Aquinas.

Writing a general study on such figures, for a broad audience, is not easy. Both authors have steered away from giving the sort of standard account which reads like an expanded encyclopaedia article. They want to avoid dullness at all costs and make their subjects lively and appealing to readers today, while also putting forward their own distinctive interpretations and ideas.

Hollingworth's book claims to be an "intellectual biography". It fails both intellectually and biographically. Augustine was a highly original and powerful, if unsystematic, philosopher and theologian. Hollingworth recounts many of Augustine's individual comments and particular thoughts, but he does not explain any of his positions or arguments clearly and in detail. Rather, his procedure is to quote a chunk of Augustine and then digress, in a way closer to free-association than philosophical analysis, citing from a seemingly endless list of contemporary writers and thinkers (Freud, C.S. Lewis, Housman, MacNeice, Durkheim, Wittgenstein). The reader is given no chance to grasp Augustine's thought or any important part of it. 

Nor does the biographical element provide much compensation. Although the narrative, in so far as there is one, is chronological, Hollingworth omits most of Augustine's life. After 60 pages of context-setting and general waffle, the next 175 pages take the reader from Augustine's birth to his conversion and the first of his surviving works. Just 15 pages later, he is on his deathbed. Hollingworth does indeed use the full range of Augustine's writings, but he does not trace out how his life and thought developed, and this omission is particularly damaging because Augustine was a thinker whose ideas changed dramatically, to the extent that, behind the real opponents of his later years, such as Pelagius and Julian of Eclanum, it can be tempting to make out the spectre of his own younger self. In this book, however, the only spectre behind, and often in front of, Augustine is that of Hollingworth; except for direct quotations, it is hard to tell which are ideas are supposed to be Augustine's, and which the author's own.

View Full Article
 
Share/Save
 
 
 
 

Post your comment

CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.